Word meaning has played a somewhat marginal role in early contemporary philosophy of language, which was primarily concerned with the structural features of sentences and showed less interest in the format of lexical representations and in the nature of the word-level input to compositional processes. Nowadays, it is well-established that the way we account for word meaning is bound to have a major impact in tipping the balance in favor or against a given picture of the fundamental properties of human language. This entry provides an overview of the way issues related to lexical meaning have been explored in analytic philosophy and a summary of relevant research on the subject in neighboring scientific domains. Though the main focus will be on philosophical problems, contributions from linguistics, psychology, neuroscience and artificial intelligence will also be considered, since research on word meaning is highly interdisciplinary.2. Historical Background
2.1 Classical Traditions
2.2 Historical-Philological Semantics
3. Philosophy of Language
3.1 Early Contemporary Views
3.2 Grounding and Lexical Competence
3.3 The Externalist Turn
3.4 Internalism
3.5 Contextualism, Minimalism, and the Lexicon
4. Linguistics
4.1 Structuralist Semantics
4.2 Generativist Semantics
4.3 Decompositional Approaches
4.4 Relational Approaches
5. Cognitive Science
5.1 Cognitive Linguistics
5.2 Psycholinguistics
5.3 Neurolinguistics
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
[size=30]1. Basics
The notions of
word and
word meaning are problematic to pin down, and this is reflected in the difficulties one encounters in defining the basic terminology of lexical semantics. In part, this depends on the fact that the words ‘word’ and ‘meaning’ themselves have multiple meanings, depending on the context and the purpose they are used for (Matthews 1991). For example, in ordinary parlance ‘word’ is ambiguous between lexeme (as in “
Color and
colour are spellings of the same word”) and lexical unit (as in “there are thirteen words in the tongue-twister
How much wood would a woodchuck chuck if a woodchuck could chuck wood?”). Let us then elucidate the notion of word in a little more detail, and specify what key questions will guide our discussion of word meaning in the rest of the entry.
1.1 The Notion of Word
The notion of word can be defined in two fundamental ways. On one side, we have
linguisticdefinitions, which attempt to characterize the notion of word by illustrating the explanatory role words play or are expected to play in the context of a formal grammar. These approaches often end up splitting the notion of word into a number of more fine-grained and theoretically manageable notions, but still tend to regard ‘word’ as a term that zeroes in on a scientifically respectable concept (e.g., Di Sciullo & Williams 1987). For example, words are the primary locus of stress and tone assignment, the basic domain of morphological conditions on affixation, clitization, compounding, and the theme of phonological and morphological processes of assimilation, vowel shift, metathesis, and reduplication (Bromberger 2011). On the other side, we have
metaphysical definitions, which attempt to elucidate the notion of word by describing the metaphysical type of words. This implies answering such questions as “what are words?”, “how should words be individuated?”, and “on what conditions two utterances count as utterances of the same word?”. For example, Kaplan (1990, 2011) has proposed to replace the orthodox type-token account of the relation between words and word occurrences with a “common currency” view on which words relate to their occurrences as continuants relate to stages in four-dimensionalist metaphysics (see the entries on
types and tokens and
identity over time). For alternative views, see McCulloch (1991), Cappelen (1999), Alward (2005), and Hawthorne & Lepore (2011).
For the purposes of this entry, we can proceed as follows. Every natural language has a
lexiconorganized into
lexical entries, which contain information about
lexemes. These are the smallest linguistic expressions that are conventionally associated with a non-compositional meaning and can be uttered in isolation to convey semantic content.
Lexemes relate to
words just like phonemes relate to phones in phonological theory. To understand the parallelism, think of the variations in the place of articulation of the phoneme /n/, which is pronounced as the voiced bilabial nasal [m] in “ten bags” and as the voiced velar nasal [ŋ] in “ten gates”. Just as phonemes are abstract representations of sets of phones (each defining one way the phoneme can be instantiated in speech), lexemes can be defined as abstract representations of sets of words (each defining one way the lexeme can be instantiated in sentences). Thus, ‘do’, ‘does’, ‘done’ and ‘doing’ are morphologically and graphically marked realizations of the same abstract lexeme
do. To wrap everything into a single formula, we can say that the
lexical entries listed in a
lexicon set the parameters defining the instantiation potential of
lexemes as
words in utterances and inscriptions (Murphy 2010). In what follows, we shall rely on an intuitive notion of word. However, the reader should bear in mind that, unless otherwise indicated, our talk of ‘word meaning’ should be understood as talk of ‘lexeme meaning’, in the above sense.
1.2 Theories of Word Meaning
As with general theories of meaning (see the entry on
theories of meaning), two kinds of theory of word meaning can be distinguished. The first type of theory, that we can label a
semantictheory of word meaning, is interested in clarifying what meaning-determining information is encoded by the lexical items of a natural language. A framework establishing that the word ‘bachelor’ encodes the lexical concept adult unmarried male would be an example of a semantic theory of word meaning. The second type of theory, that we can label a
foundationaltheory of word meaning, is interested in singling out the facts whereby lexical expressions come to have the semantic properties they have for their users. A framework investigating the dynamics of linguistic change and social coordination in virtue of which the word ‘bachelor’ has been assigned the function of expressing the lexical concept adult unmarried male would be an example of a foundational theory of word meaning. Obviously, the endorsement of a given semantic theory is bound to place important constraints on the claims one might propose about the foundational attributes of word meaning, and
vice versa. Semantic and foundational concerns are often interdependent, and it is difficult to find theories of word meaning which are either purely semantic or purely foundational. For example, Ludlow (2014) establishes a strong correlation between the underdetermination of lexical concepts (a semantic matter) and the processes of linguistic entrenchment whereby discourse partners converge on the assignation of shared meanings to lexical expressions (a foundational matter). However, semantic and foundational theories remain in principle different and designed to answer partly non-overlapping sets of questions. Our focus will be on
semantic theories of word meaning, i.e., on theories that try to provide an answer to such questions as “what is the nature of word meaning?”, “what do we know when we know the meaning of a word?”, and “what (kind of) information must an agent associate to the words of a language
L in order to be a competent user of the lexicon of
L?”. However, we will engage in foundational considerations whenever necessary to clarify how a given theoretical framework addresses issues in the domain of a semantic theory.
[size=30]2. Historical Background[/size]
The study of word meaning acquired the status of a mature academic enterprise in the 19
thcentury, with the birth of historical-philological semantics (
Section 2.2). Yet, matters related to word meaning had been the subject of much debate in earlier times. Word meaning constituted a prominent topic of inquiry in three classical traditions: speculative etymology, rhetoric, and lexicography (Meier-Oeser 2011; Geeraerts 2013).
2.1 Classical Traditions
To understand what
speculative etymology amounts to, it is useful to refer to the
Cratylus(383a-d), where Plato presents his well-known naturalist thesis about word meaning: natural kind terms express the essence of the objects they name and words are appropriate to their referents insofar as they describe what their referents are (see the entry on
Plato’s Cratylus). The task of speculative etymology is to break down the surface features of word forms and recover the descriptive (often phonoiconic) rationale that motivated their genesis. For example, the Greek word ‘
anthrôpos’ can be broken down into
anathrôn ha opôpe, which translates as “one who reflects on what he has seen”: the word used to denote humans reflects their being the only animal species which possesses the combination of vision and intelligence. More in Malkiel (1993), Fumaroli (1999), and Del Bello (2007).
The primary aim of the
rhetorical tradition was the study of figures of speech. Some of these affect structural variables such as the linear order of the words occurring in a sentence (e.g., parallelism, climax, anastrophe); others are semantic and arise upon using lexical expressions in a way not intended by their normal meaning (e.g., metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche). Although originated for stylistic and literary purposes, the identification of regular patterns in the figurative use of words initiated by classical rhetoric provided a first organized framework to investigate the semantic flexibility of words, and stimulated an interest in our ability to use lexical expressions beyond the boundaries of their literal meaning. More in Kennedy (1994), Herrick (2004), and Toye (2013).
Finally,
lexicography and the practice of writing dictionaries played an important role in systematizing the descriptive data on which later inquiry would rely to illuminate the relationship between words and their meaning. Putnam’s (1970) claim that it was the phenomenon of writing (and needing) dictionaries that gave rise to the idea of a semantic theory is probably an overstatement. But lexicography certainly had an impact on the development of modern theories of word meaning. The practice of separating dictionary entries via lemmatization and defining them through a combination of semantically simpler elements provided a stylistic and methodological paradigm for much subsequent research on lexical phenomena, such as decompositional theories of word meaning. More in Béjoint (2000), Jackson (2002), and Hanks (2013).[/size]
الثلاثاء مارس 08, 2016 9:07 am من طرف free men