Sense-perception has long been a preoccupation of philosophers. One pervasive and traditional problem, sometimes called “the Problem of Perception”, is created by the phenomena of perceptual illusion and hallucination: if these kinds of error are possible, how can perception be what we ordinarily understand it to be, an openness to and awareness of the world? The present entry is about how these possibilities of error challenge the intelligibility of the phenomenon of perception, and how the major theories of experience in the last century are best understood as responses to this challenge.1.2 Awareness
2. The Problem of Perception
2.1 The Argument from Illusion
2.2 The Argument from Hallucination
3. Theories of Experience
3.1 The Sense-Datum Theory
3.1.1 The Sense-Datum Theory and The Problem of Perception
3.1.2 Indirect Realism and Phenomenalism
3.1.3 Objections to the Sense-Datum Theory
3.2 The Adverbial Theory
3.2.1 The Adverbial Theory and the Problem of Perception
3.2.2 The Adverbial Theory and Qualia
3.2.3 Objections to the Adverbial Theory
3.3 The Intentionalist Theory
3.3.1 The Intentionalist Theory and the Problem of Perception
3.3.2 Sources of the Intentionalist Theory
3.3.3 The Intentional Content of Perceptual Experience
3.3.4 Objections to the Intentionalist Theory
3.4 The Naive Realist Theory
3.4.1 The Naive Realist Theory
3.4.2 The Naive Realist Theory and The Argument from Illusion
3.4.3 The Naive Realist Theory and The Argument from Hallucination
3.4.4 Objections and The Development of Disjunctivism
4. Conclusion
Bibliography
Further reading
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
[size=30]1. The Ordinary Conception of Perceptual Experience
In this section we spell out the ordinary conception of perceptual experience. There are two central aspects to this:
Openness (
§1.1) and
Awareness (
§1.2).
1.1 Openness
On our ordinary conception of perceptual experience, perceptual experience is a form of “openness to the world” McDowell (1994: 111). We understand this more precisely as follows:
Openness: Perceptual experience, in its character, involves the presentation (as) of ordinary mind-independent objects to a subject, and such objects are experienced as
present or
theresuch that the character of experience is immediately responsive to the character of its objects.
To clarify this, we can break it down into two components:
Mind-Independence (
§1.1.1), and
Presence (
§1.1.2).
1.1.1 Mind-Independence
The first component of
Openness is,
Mind-Independence: perceptual experience involves the presentation (as) of ordinary mind-independent objects.
On ‘object’: we assume a broad understanding of ‘object’ to encompass perceptible entities in mind-independent reality including material objects, but also features and other entities (e.g., events, quantities of stuff).
Mind-Independence is thus a claim otherwise expressed as follows: perceptual experience is a presentation of, or is as of, a public, mind-independent
subject-matter. On ‘ordinary’:
Mind-Independence concerns
familiar perceptible things, things that we admit as part of common sense ontology.
As P.F. Strawson argued, reflection on ordinary perceptual experience supports a characterization of it in terms of
Mind-Independence: “mature sensible experience (in general) presents itself as, in Kantian phrase, an immediate consciousness of the existence of things outside us” (1979: 97). Strawson begins his argument by asking how someone would typically respond to a request for a description of their current visual experience. He says that it is natural to give the following kind of answer: “I see the red light of the setting sun filtering through the black and thickly clustered branches of the elms; I see the dappled deer grazing in groups on the vivid green grass…” (1979: 97). There are two ideas implicit in this answer. One is that the description talks about objects and properties which are, on the face of it, things distinct from this particular experience. The other is that the description is “rich”, describing the nature of the experience in terms of concepts like deer and elms and the setting sun. The description of the experience is not merely in terms of simple shapes and colours; but in terms of the things we encounter in the “lived world” in all their complexity. As Heidegger puts it,
[/size]
- اقتباس :
- We never … originally and really perceive a throng of sensations, e.g., tones and noises, in the appearance of things…; rather, we hear the storm whistling in the chimney, we hear the three-engine aeroplane, we hear the Mercedes in immediate distinction from the Volkswagen. Much closer to us than any sensations are the things themselves. We hear the door slam in the house, and never hear acoustic sensations or mere sounds. (Heidegger (1977: 156); quoted in Smith (2002: 105))
[size]
It may be that descriptions of experience like this involve a commitment to the existence of things outside the experience; but surely it is possible to describe experience without this commitment? So let us suppose that we ask our imagined perceiver to repeat their description without committing themselves to the existence of things outside their experience, but without falsifying how their experience seems to them. Strawson claims that the best way for them to respond is to say “I had a visual experience such as it would have been natural to describe by saying that I saw…” and then to add the previous description of the trees and the deer etc. We give a description of our experience in terms of the ordinary objects of our world. And we do this even if we are trying not to commit ourselves to the existence of these objects.
Strawson’s claim that perceptual experience strikes us as if it satisfies what we’re calling
Mind-Independence is not a philosophical theory, one that would (for example) refute scepticism, the view that we cannot know anything about the mind-independent world (see the entry on
skepticism). Rather, it should be a starting point for philosophical reflection on experience (1979: 94). This is why this intuitive datum of consciousness is not supposed to rule out idealism, the view that the objects and properties we perceive are in fact mind-dependent (see the entry on
idealism). The idealist need not disagree with Strawson that reflection on ordinary experience supports
Mind-Independence. They will just hold that, for philosophical reasons, this is not how experience really is.
Mind-Independence, they can say, is intuitively appealing but ultimately false as a characterization of experience and its objects.
1.1.2 Presence
The second component of
Openness itself involves two components. First, the phenomenal character of an experience has something to do with its presented objects: experience is,
in its character, a presentation of, or as of, ordinary objects; and second the character of perceptual experience involves the presentation of ordinary objects as
present or
there in that it is immediately responsive to the character of its objects.
Presence: the character of perceptual experience itself involves the presentation (as) of ordinary objects in such a way that it is immediately responsive to the character of its presented objects.
When we reflect upon how the phenomenal character of experience is, and try to “turn inwards” to describe the nature of the experience itself, the best way to do this is to describe the objects of experience and how they seem to us. It seems a simple matter to move to the further claim that the way these objects actually are is part of what determines the phenomenal character of an experience.
But this is to move too fast. For what can be said here about experience can also be said about belief: it is widely accepted that if I want to reflect upon the nature of my beliefs, the best way to do this is to describe the object or content of my belief: that is, what it is in the world that my belief is about. The things my beliefs are about can be as ‘objective’ as the things I perceive. So what is distinctive of the dependence of perceptual experience on its objects?
One answer is that when an object is perceptually experienced, it is experienced as “there”, “given” or “present to the mind” in a way in which it is not in belief, thought and many other mental states and events. Experience seems to involve a particular kind of “presence to the mind”. This “presence” goes beyond the mere fact that the objects of experience must exist in order for the experience to be veridical. For the objects of knowledge must exist too, but states of knowledge do not, as such, have presence in the same way as perceptual experiences—except, of course, in the case when one knows something is there by perceiving it. (Compare here the phenomenon Scott Sturgeon calls “scene immediacy” (2000: Chapter 1)).[/size]
الثلاثاء مارس 15, 2016 11:38 am من طرف free men